Popular Culture Review Vol. 13, No. 2, Summer 2002 | Page 19

Back to Bazin 15 Bazin founded his entire theory” (25). Alexandre Astruc seems to have anticipated such a development long ago. “The cinema,” he opined, “is not an eternal art. Its forms are not unchanging. Each of the aspects that it reveals is linked inevitably to the psychology o f a period" (emphasis added, quoted in Bordwell 46). Keeping in mind Astruc’s postulation, it is possible to conceive of the transition in film from documentation to simulation as a process parallel to that of refashioning the human body through cosmetic surgery. In many ways, the manipulation of the image by digitization is similar to the manipulation of the body by the scalpel. Both operations are symptomatic of the emergence of an increasingly prosthetic culture. Intriguingly, filmic and corporeal surgery no less than photography aim to resist processes of decay. As Bazin submits, the latter “does not create eternity, as art does, it embalms time, rescuing it simply from its proper corruption” (14). Paradoxically, however, where the photograph prevents corruption by preserving the object, surgery attempts to do the same by transforming it. Inevitably, this enge nders yet another contradiction, since surgical alteration is often a conservational procedure which curtails the continuity of that sameness it attempts to insulate from the corruption of time. As computer surgery modifies the substance of the body of the photographic image, film becomes not the redemption but the negation of physical reahty. In assuming what one might call a Neo-Bazinian position vis-a-vis cinema and the photographic, I am acutely aware of the risk of embracing a thesis that in theoretical terms appears reactionary, or at least antiquated. The disputant will no doubt ask why I worry so much about the material basis of representational forms, thinking this inconsequential in relation to the effects and messages fictional representations are bound to convey irrespective of the nature of their materiality. Moreover, she may add that phenomenology overrides o n to lo g y th a t is, what does it matter that the stunning image of the chateau by the lake and the Swiss Alps in James Cameron’s True Lies (1994) is devoid of photographic referentiality as long as viewers approach it as a reproduction of actual space? Pictorial verisimihtude, one may continue, has not so much to do with the substance of its source as with the machinations of visual perception. When Stephen Prince in a 1996 article in Film Quarterly probed the consequences of the following question - “What are the implications of computer-generated imagery for representation in cinema, particularly for concepts of photographically based realism?” (27) - he concluded that perceptual realism “can encompass both unreal images and those which are referentially fictional but perceptually realistic” (32). He thus suggests that the effects of perceptual reahsm supersede the problem of material realism. Even if most viewers would fail to make a phenomenological distinction between photographic and computer-generated imagery, one may still identify a set of problems related to postphotographic practice and the status of the filmic. Firstly, film is not a mere receptacle for a kind of extra-filmic content we call