European Policy Analysis Volume 2, Number 1, Spring 2016 | Page 156

Knowing the Future: Theories of Time in Policy Analysis making procedures. Instead of problem solving, the best actors can do is using trialand-error procedures. Choice is made not on a rational basis but as spontaneous selection from a fluid and incalculable stream of events. Sometimes, this strategy of “temporal sorting” means searching a problem for an already available solution. Time is scarce and so is attention. In contrast to the first group of theories, rationality is bounded because of limited cognitive and organizational resources (Kahneman 2011; Simon 1982). More importantly, problems, solutions, and politics flow more or less independently of each other like streams of events, regardless of the policy agenda or the strategies of actors. Sometimes, an opportunity window opens up and can be used to couple problems, solutions, and/ or politics. It all comes down the right timing. The capability of political action depends on different zones of attentions, much like Schütz has described them: “There is a relatively small kernel that is clear, distinct and consistent in itself. This kernel is surrounded by zones of various gradations of vagueness, obscurity, and ambiguity. There follow zones of things just taken for granted, blind beliefs, bare suppositions, mere guesswork […]. And finally, there are regions of our complete ignorance” (1959, 78). Ambiguity and ignorance are high. Under these circumstances, the main mode of political action is temporal manipulation (Zahariadis 2003, 14–16; 2015). The presentations of problems as being urgent, the use of symbols such as a burning flag to raise awareness, “salami tactics” to enable sequential decision making, or the acceleration of procedures help to focus debates and move them into a desired direction. In his analysis of deadlines, Zahariadis has shown that delimiting time horizons tends to dramatically change the temporal rhythm of the policy process. Deadlines are not politically neutral. Instead, they are “political devices” changing the long-term orientation of policymakers while accelerating decision making. By inducing an artificial termination, they reduce political conflicts, facilitate a more innovative and uninhibited policy style—but may also lead to a decrease in participation and to less democratic dynamics of exclusion (Zahariadis 2015). For all these reasons, theories of policymaking by time tend to be skeptical about knowing the future. Under conditions of ambiguity, knowledge about the future may change at every moment. Policymakers carry on in an incremental fashion, aiming at taking their opportunities for both attention and action as the policy stream goes on. 5. Times of Policymaking A third group of theories of time is inspired by pragmatist interpretations of time and the sociology of knowledge and culture (Berger and Luckmann 1967; Elias 1984; Nowotny 1994). It builds on William James’ (1890) distinction between “knowledge about” and “knowledge of acquaintance”, a basic difference also for Schütz who makes use of it in his constitutional theory of social reality (1959, 78). In modern societies, much knowledge is derived not from immediate observation but through highly objectified, shared systems of sense-making imposed on us by others in societal interactions (Schütz 1976; Srubar 1988). 156