Connections Quarterly Winter 2014 - Integrity | Page 15

w Since Greene, like other neo-evolutionists, can’t prove his case by observation, he draws on other resources, from neuroscientific data about the parts of our brain that are engaged when we consider moral dilemmas or have an instant revulsion against a scenario, to designed experiments eliciting reactions that the participants then review and explain. Add to this his extensive knowledge of ethical theories from Aristotle to John Rawls, and you have a serious explorer of our ethical geography. To simplify, Greene’s thesis is that while “In everyday life we’re much better off listening to our moral instincts,” or, as he puts it, operating in a sort of auto-focus mode, when it comes to subjects where different groups seem to have incompatible moral instincts, we need to shift into manual mode, using reason to assess the validity of our intuitions. (Greene acknowledges his debt to Daniel Kahneman’s Thinking, Fast and Slow.) He notes that we are skilled at rationalizing our preferred morality by such devices as “biased fairness”–it’s unfair for some people to free ride on the hard work of others, says the conservative, but it’s unfair that a wealthy person should pay a lower tax rate on capital gains and other investments than a worker pays on wages, says the liberal. He argues that the appeal to rights “function as an intellectual free pass, a trump card that renders evidence irrelevant,” because “whatever you and your fellow tribes-people feel, you can always posit the existence of a right that corresponds to your feelings.” Greene borrows the psychological term “cognitively impenetrable” to describe the imperviousness of these rights assertions to rational analysis. “ Greene has drawn a revealing picture of the moral quandaries we, )